The report comes at a pertinent time for mental health research; last year the same organisation questioned the value
of psychiatric diagnosis altogether. This new document seems to cast
doubt on many received wisdoms about schizophrenia, even questioning
whether it is an illness. So what is happening here?
Radical shifts
Schizophrenia has been a controversial and shifting diagnosis since the
word was coined by Eugen Bleuler in 1911. Its name has undergone quite
radical changes in meaning, moving from being seen as a progressive
brain disease, to being thought of as a series of “reactions” in the
first DSM
(the American manual of mental disorders) to increasingly being defined
since the 1980s as a neuro-developmental disorder in psychiatric
research.
In 1979, the trenchant critic of psychiatry Thomas Szasz called it
“psychiatry’s sacred symbol” and wondered at length how psychiatry was
able to get away with the perpetration of a crucial and
profession-sustaining “myth”.
Some of the iconoclasm faded, but in recent years a new group of sceptics (referred to as “schizophrenia’s scientific critics” by the philosopher Jeffrey Poland) have challenged the diagnosis of schizophrenia with renewed rigour.
In 1991 the academic clinical psychologist Mary Boyle published a book
with a strikingly bold thesis. Writing under the provocative title
Schizophrenia: A Scientific Delusion? she proceeded to outline how
putative psychological illness was far less coherent than it has long
been taken to be. Consequently, she has argued, it should be dispensed
with as soon as possible, as it only serves to perpetuate a confused
view of mental health problems. A similar view recently found its way
into a heated discussion on the comments section of an article on The Conversation.
Meanwhile, many academics continue to embrace schizophrenia more readily (though still not without caution). In his book-length introduction
to the topic psychologist Michael Green says that the particular set of
behaviours and experiences which currently attracts a DSM diagnosis of
schizophrenia is unlikely to be underpinned by a single genetic profile.
Future research should “let go” of schizophrenia as currently conceived
and focus on different ways of classifying the problems we associate
with that label. Thomas Insel, director of America’s National Institute
for Mental Health, agrees with this view.
However, Green’s book still treats the diagnosis as a meaningful
category with a real need for psychiatric intervention, and neither he
nor Insel are social constructionists about schizophrenia. How can we
square this with the way they also apparently encourage us to relinquish
the idea, much as one gives up a bad habit?
Revolutionaries and reformists
We can think about the different views on schizophrenia as
“revolutionary” and “reformist”. Reformers like Green recognise that the
concept is unwieldy and insufficiently precise. They are not holding
their breath for discovery of a single gene or simple biomarker for
schizophrenia, and they may balk at the idea
that it is a “progressive, degenerative brain disease”, but they have
no problem with continuing to talk about schizophrenia the “disorder”,
“illness” or “syndrome”.
Perhaps what puts most water between these two groups is the degree of
urgency they respectively feel about getting rid of the label
“schizophrenia”. For “revolutionaries”, schizophrenia is more of a
barrier than an effective tool for clinical communication, useless at
best and a form of denigration at worst.
“Schizophrenia” is used to justify coercive treatments, it exacerbates mental health stigma, and it has even evolved to become a moderately racist label. Suggestive research
on the phenomenon of “stereotype threat” points to the possibility that
being known to have the diagnosis may even, under certain conditions,
have an exacerbating effect on the psychological and social difficulties
of people who meet the criteria. “Get rid of the idea altogether!” say
revolutionaries.
But one difficulty with such a move is in knowing what its implications
should be for our understanding of the problems that merit a diagnosis.
Some critics dispute the idea that these individuals are “ill”, though
this doesn’t fit with everyone’s first-hand experience.
Furthermore, in the absence of a widely agreed upon definition of
“mentally ill” it’s hard to see how the question could be resolved one
way or another. As psychologist Richard Bentall has said recently:
“The problem has become not whether to replace schizophrenia, but what
to replace it with”. There are many ideas, but we still lack consensus.
To ask whether schizophrenia “really exists” is somewhat beside the
point. Revolutionaries can, with good reason, say “no”; Schizophrenia is
a metaphor, and an often misleading, overly reified one at that.
However, reformists can justly point out that while DSM schizophrenia is
a historically contingent construction, there is nonetheless an
important, often debilitating, set of experiences in its vicinity which
we cannot wish away. Arguments over terminology aside, it is the nature
of these experiences which holds the most interest to researchers and
clinicians, and we still know far too little.
The BPS report should serve as a reminder to think wisely about the
term “schizophrenia”. Without underplaying the seriousness of the
problems it connotes, we should remain wary of it. We also urgently need
to prevent its use from needlessly limiting the opportunities people
have for living the life they want.
However the report is not without problems; arguably it focuses too
much attention on hallucinations and delusions at the expense of
“negative” or disorganised symptoms. Equally, it questionably concludes
that CBT for psychosis can be effective, despite doubts
from the very researchers that it cites. There is much to agree with in
“Understanding Psychosis”, but many of the debates touched on here are
far from settled.
No comments:
Post a Comment